The Perfect Critic
by T.S.Eliot
I
"Eriger en lois ses impressions personnelles, c'est le grand effort d'un
homme s'il est sinc┬re."!Lettres ┐ 'Amazone.
COLERIDGE was perhaps the greatest of English critics, and in a sense the last.
After Coleridge we have Matthew Arnold; but Arnold!I think it will be
conceded!was rather a propagandist for criticism than a critic, a popularizer
rather than a creator of ideas. So long as this island remains an island (and we
are no nearer the Continent than were Arnold's contemporaries) the work of
Arnold will be important; it is still a bridge across the Channel, and it will
always have been good sense. Since Arnold's attempt to correct his countrymen,
English criticism has followed two directions. When a distinguished critic
observed recently, in a newspaper article, that "poetry is the most highly
organized form of intellectual activity," we were conscious that we were
reading neither Coleridge nor Arnold. Not only have the words
"organized" and "activity," occurring together in this
phrase, that familiar vague suggestion of the scientific vocabulary which is
characteristic of modern writing, but one asked questions which Coleridge and
Arnold would not have permitted one to ask. How is it, for instance, that poetry
is more "highly organized" than astronomy, physics, or pure
mathematics, which we imagine to be, in relation to the scientist who practises
them, "intellectual activity" of a pretty highly organized type?
"Mere strings of words," our critic continues with felicity and truth,
"flung like dabs of paint across a blank canvas, may awaken surprise ...
but have no significance whatever in the history of literature." The
phrases by which Arnold is best known may be inadequate, they may assemble more
doubts than they dispel, but they usually have some meaning. And if a phrase
like "the most highly organized form of intellectual activity" is the
highest organization of thought of which contemporary criticism, in a
distinguished representative, is capable, then, we conclude, modern criticism is
degenerate.
The verbal disease above noticed may be reserved for diagnosis by and by. It is
not a disease from which Mr. Arthur Symons (for the quotation was, of course,
not from Mr. Symons) notably suffers. Mr. Symons represents the other tendency;
he is a representative of what is always called "?sthetic criticism"
or "impressionistic criticism." And it is this form of criticism which
I propose to examine at once. Mr. Symons, the critical successor of Pater, and
partly of Swinburne (I fancy that the phrase "sick or sorry" is the
common property of all three), is the "impressionistic critic." He, if
anyone, would be said to expose a sensitive and cultivated mind!cultivated,
that is, by the accumulation of a considerable variety of impressions from all
the arts and several languages!before an "object"; and his
criticism, if anyone's, would be said to exhibit to us, like the plate, the
faithful record of the impressions, more numerous or more refined than our own,
upon a mind more sensitive than our own. A record, we observe, which is also an
interpretation, a translation; for it must itself impose impressions upon us,
and these impressions are as much created as transmitted by the criticism. I do
not say at once that this is Mr. Symons; but it is the
"impressionistic" critic, and the impressionistic critic is supposed
to be Mr. Symons.
At hand is a volume which we may test. Ten of these thirteen essays deal
with single plays of Shakespeare, and it is therefore fair to take one of these
ten as a specimen of the book:
Antony and Cleopatra is the most wonderful, I think, of all Shakespeare's
plays...
and Mr. Symons reflects that Cleopatra is the most wonderful of all women:
The queen who ends the dynasty of the Ptolemies has been the star of poets, a
malign star shedding baleful light, from Horace and Propertius down to Victor
Hugo; and it is not to poets only...
What, we ask, is this for? as a page on Cleopatra, and on her possible origin in
the dark lady of the Sonnets, unfolds itself. And we find, gradually, that this
is not an essay on a work of art or a work of intellect; but that Mr. Symons is
living through the play as one might live it through in the theatre; recounting,
commenting:
In her last days Cleopatra touches a certain elevation ... she would die a
thousand times, rather than live to be a mockery and a scorn in men's mouths ...
she is a woman to the last ... so she dies ... the plays ends with a touch of
grave pity...
Presented in this rather unfair way, torn apart like the leaves of an artichoke,
the impressions of Mr. Symons come to resemble a common type of popular literary
lecture, in which the stories of plays or novels are retold, the motives of the
characters set forth, and the work of art therefore made easier for the
beginner. But this is not Mr. Symons' reason for writing. The reason why we find
a similarity between his essay and this form of education is that Antony and
Cleopatra is a play with which we are pretty well acquainted, and of which we
have, therefore, our own impressions. We can please ourselves with our own
impressions of the characters and their emotions; and we do not find the
impressions of another person, however sensitive, very significant. But if we
can recall the time when we were ignorant of the French symbolists, and met with
The Symbolist Movement in Literature, we remember that book as an introduction
to wholly new feelings, as a revelation. After we have read Verlaine and
Laforgue and Rimbaud and return to Mr. Symons' book, we may find that our own
impressions dissent from his. The book has not, perhaps, a permanent value for
the one reader, but it has led to results of permanent importance for him.
The question is not whether Mr. Symons' impressions are "true" or
"false." So far as you can isolate the "impression," the
pure feeling, it is, of course, neither true nor false. The point is that you
never rest at the pure feeling; you react in one of two ways, or, as I believe
Mr. Symons does, in a mixture of the two ways. The moment you try to put the
impressions into words, you either begin to analyse and construct, to "└riger
en lois," or you begin to create something else. It is significant that
Swinburne, by whose poetry Mr. Symons may at one time have been influenced, is
one man in his poetry and a different man in his criticism; to this extent and
in this respect only, that he is satisfying a different impulse; he is
criticizing, expounding, arranging. You may say this is not the criticism of a
critic, that it is emotional, not intellectual!though of this there are two
opinions, but it is in the direction of analysis and construction, a beginning
to "└riger en lois," and not in the direction of creation. So I infer
that Swinburne found an adequate outlet for the creative impulse in his poetry;
and none of it was forced back and out through his critical prose. The style of
the latter is essentially a prose style; and Mr. Symons' prose is much more like
Swinburne's poetry than it is like his prose. I imagine!though here one's
thought is moving in almost complete darkness!that Mr. Symons is far more
disturbed, far more profoundly affected, by his reading than was Swinburne, who
responded rather by a violent and immediate and comprehensive burst of
admiration which may have left him internally unchanged. The disturbance in Mr.
Symons is almost, but not quite, to the point of creating; the reading sometimes
fecundates his emotions to produce something new which is not criticism, but is
not the expulsion, the ejection, the birth of creativeness.
The type is not uncommon, although Mr. Symons is far superior to most of the
type. Some writers are essentially of the type that reacts in excess of the
stimulus, making something new out of the impressions, but suffer from a defect
of vitality or an obscure obstruction which prevents nature from taking its
course. Their sensibility alters the object, but never transforms it. Their
reaction is that of the ordinary emotional person developed to an exceptional
degree. For this ordinary emotional person, experiencing a work of art, has a
mixed critical and creative reaction. It is made up of comment and opinion, and
also new emotions which are vaguely applied to his own life. The sentimental
person, in whom a work of art arouses all sorts of emotions which have nothing
to do with that work of art whatever, but are accidents of personal association,
is an incomplete artist. For in an artist these suggestions made by a work of
art, which are purely personal, become fused with a multitude of other
suggestions from multitudinous experience, and result in the production of a new
object which is no longer purely personal, because it is a work of art itself.
It would be rash to speculate, and is perhaps impossible to determine, what is
unfulfilled in Mr. Symons' charming verse that overflows into his critical
prose. Certainly we may say that in Swinburne's verse the circuit of impression
and expression is complete; and Swinburne was therefore able, in his criticism,
to be more a critic than Mr. Symons. This gives us an intimation why the artist
is!each within his own limitations!oftenest to be depended upon as a critic;
his criticism will be criticism, and not the satisfaction of a suppressed
creative wish!which, in most other persons, is apt to interfere fatally.
Before considering what the proper critical reaction of artistic sensibility is,
how far criticism is "feeling" and how far "thought," and
what sort of "thought" is permitted, it may be instructive to prod a
little into that other temperament, so different from Mr. Symons', which issues
in generalities such as that quoted near the beginning of this article.
II
"L'└crivain de style abstrait est presque toujours un sentimental, du
moins un sensitif. L'└crivain artiste n'est presque jamais un sentimental, et
tr┬s rarement un sensitif."!Le Probl┬me du Style.
The statement already quoted, that "poetry is the most highly organized
form of intellectual activity," may be taken as a specimen of the abstract
style in criticism. The confused distinction which exists in most heads between
"abstract" and "concrete" is due not so much to a manifest
fact of the existence of two types of mind, an abstract and a concrete, as to
the existence of another type of mind, the verbal, or philosophic. I, of course,
do not imply any general condemnation of philosophy; I am, for the moment, using
the word "philosophic" to cover the unscientific ingredients of
philosophy; to cover, in fact, the greater part of the philosophic output of the
last hundred years. There are two ways in which a word may be
"abstract." It may have (the word "activity," for example) a
meaning which cannot be grasped by appeal to any of the senses; its apprehension
may require a deliberate suppression of analogies of visual or muscular
experience, which is none the less an effort of imagination.
"Activity" will mean for the trained scientist, if he employ the term,
either nothing at all or something still more exact than anything it suggests to
us. If we are allowed to accept certain remarks of Pascal and Mr. Bertrand
Russell about mathematics, we believe that the mathematician deals with
objects!if he will permit us to call them objects!which directly affect his
sensibility. And during a good part of history the philosopher endeavoured to
deal with objects which he believed to be of the same exactness as the
mathematician's. Finally Hegel arrived, and if not perhaps the first, he was
certainly the most prodigious exponent of emotional systematization, dealing
with his emotions as if they were definite objects which had aroused those
emotions. His followers have as a rule taken for granted that words have
definite meanings, overlooking the tendency of words to become indefinite
emotions. (No one who had not witnessed the event could imagine the conviction
in the tone of Professor Eucken as he pounded the table and exclaimed Was ist
Geist? Geist ist...) If verbalism were confined to professional philosophers, no
harm would be done. But their corruption has extended very far. Compare a
medi?val theologian or mystic, compare a seventeenth-century preacher, with any
"liberal" sermon since Schleiermacher, and you will observe that words
have changed their meanings. What they have lost is definite, and what they have
gained is indefinite.
The vast accumulations of knowledge!or at least of information!deposited by
the nineteenth century have been responsible for an equally vast ignorance. When
there is so much to be known, when there are so many fields of knowledge in
which the same words are used with different meanings, when every one knows a
little about a great many things, it becomes increasingly difficult for anyone
to know whether he knows what he is talking about or not. And when we do not
know, or when we do not know enough, we tend always to substitute emotions for
thoughts. The sentence so frequently quoted in this essay will serve for an
example of this process as well as any, and may be profitably contrasted with
the opening phrases of the Posterior Analytics. Not only all knowledge, but all
feeling, is in perception. The inventor of poetry as the most highly organized
form of intellectual activity was not engaged in perceiving when he composed
this definition; he had nothing to be aware of except his own emotion about
"poetry." He was, in fact, absorbed in a very different
"activity" not only from that of Mr. Symons, but from that of
Aristotle.
Aristotle is a person who has suffered from the adherence of persons who must be
regarded less as his disciples than as his sectaries. One must be firmly
distrustful of accepting Aristotle in a canonical spirit; this is to lose the
whole living force of him. He was primarily a man of not only remarkable but
universal intelligence; and universal intelligence means that he could apply his
intelligence to anything. The ordinary intelligence is good only for certain
classes of objects; a brilliant man of science, if he is interested in poetry at
all, may conceive grotesque judgments: like one poet because he reminds him of
himself, or another because he expresses emotions which he admires; he may use
art, in fact, as the outlet for the egotism which is suppressed in his own
speciality. But Aristotle had none of these impure desires to satisfy; in
whatever sphere of interest, he looked solely and steadfastly at the object; in
his short and broken treatise he provides an eternal example!not of laws, or
even of method, for there is no method except to be very intelligent, but of
intelligence itself swiftly operating the analysis of sensation to the point of
principle and definition.
It is far less Aristotle than Horace who has been the model for criticism up to
the nineteenth century. A precept, such as Horace, or Boileau gives us, is
merely an unfinished analysis. It appears as a law, a rule, because it does not
appear in its most general form; it is empirical. When we understand necessity,
as Spinoza knew, we are free because we assent. The dogmatic critic, who lays
down a rule, who affirms a value, has left his labour incomplete. Such
statements may often be justifiable as a saving of time; but in matters of great
importance the critic must not coerce, and he must not make judgments of worse
and better. He must simply elucidate: the reader will form the correct judgment
for himself.
And again, the purely "technical" critic!the critic, that is, who
writes to expound some novelty or impart some lesson to practitioners of an
art!can be called a critic only in a narrow sense. He may be analysing
perceptions and the means for arousing perceptions, but his aim is limited and
is not the disinterested exercise of intelligence. The narrowness of the aim
makes easier the detection of the merit or feebleness of the work; even of these
writers there are very few!so that their "criticism" is of great
importance within its limits. So much suffices for Campion. Dryden is far more
disinterested; he displays much free intelligence; and yet even Dryden!or any
literary critic of the seventeenth century!is not quite a free mind, compared,
for instance, with such a mind as Rochefoucauld's. There is always a tendency to
legislate rather than to inquire, to revise accepted laws, even to overturn, but
to reconstruct out of the same material. And the free intelligence is that which
is wholly devoted to inquiry.
Coleridge, again, whose natural abilities, and some of whose performances, are
probably more remarkable than those of any other modern critic, cannot be
estimated as an intelligence completely free. The nature of the restraint in his
case is quite different from that which limited the seventeenth-century critics,
and is much more personal. Coleridge's metaphysical interest was quite genuine,
and was, like most metaphysical interest, an affair of his emotions. But a
literary critic should have no emotions except those immediately provoked by a
work of art!and these (as I have already hinted) are, when valid, perhaps not
to be called emotions at all. Coleridge is apt to take leave of the data of
criticism, and arouse the suspicion that he has been diverted into a
metaphysical hare-and-hounds. His end does not always appear to be the return to
the work of art with improved perception and intensified, because more
conscious, enjoyment; his centre of interest changes, his feelings are impure.
In the derogatory sense he is more "philosophic" than Aristotle. For
everything that Aristotle says illuminates the literature which is the occasion
for saying it; but Coleridge only now and then. It is one more instance of the
pernicious effect of emotion.
Aristotle had what is called the scientific mind!a mind which, as it is rarely
found among scientists except in fragments, might better be called the
intelligent mind. For there is no other intelligence than this, and so far as
artists and men of letters are intelligent (we may doubt whether the level of
intelligence among men of letters is as high as among men of science) their
intelligence is of this kind. Sainte-Beuve was a physiologist by training; but
it is probable that his mind, like that of the ordinary scientific specialist,
was limited in its interest, and that this was not, primarily, an interest in
art. If he was a critic, there is no doubt that he was a very good one; but we
may conclude that he earned some other name. Of all modern critics, perhaps Remy
de Gourmont had most of the general intelligence of Aristotle. An amateur,
though an excessively able amateur, in physiology, he combined to a remarkable
degree sensitiveness, erudition, sense of fact and sense of history, and
generalizing power.
We assume the gift of a superior sensibility. And for sensibility wide and
profound reading does not mean merely a more extended pasture. There is not
merely an increase of understanding, leaving the original acute impression
unchanged. The new impressions modify the impressions received from the objects
already known. An impression needs to be constantly refreshed by new impressions
in order that it may persist at all; it needs to take its place in a system of
impressions. And this system tends to become articulate in a generalized
statement of literary beauty.
There are, for instance, many scattered lines and tercets in the Divine Comedy
which are capable of transporting even a quite uninitiated reader, just
sufficiently acquainted with the roots of the language to decipher the meaning,
to an impression of overpowering beauty. This impression may be so deep that no
subsequent study and understanding will intensify it. But at this point the
impression is emotional; the reader in the ignorance which we postulate is
unable to distinguish the poetry from an emotional state aroused in himself by
the poetry, a state which may be merely an indulgence of his own emotions. The
poetry may be an accidental stimulus. The end of the enjoyment of poetry is a
pure contemplation from which all the accidents of personal emotion are removed;
thus we aim to see the object as it really is and find a meaning for the words
of Arnold. And without a labour which is largely a labour of the intelligence,
we are unable to attain that stage of vision amor intellectualis Dei.
Such considerations, cast in this general form, may appear commonplaces. But I
believe that it is always opportune to call attention to the torpid superstition
that appreciation is one thing, and "intellectual" criticism something
else. Appreciation in popular psychology is one faculty, and criticism another,
an arid cleverness building theoretical scaffolds upon one's own perceptions or
those of others. On the contrary, the true generalization is not something
superposed upon an accumulation of perceptions; the perceptions do not, in a
really appreciative mind, accumulate as a mass, but form themselves as a
structure; and criticism is the statement in language of this structure; it is a
development of sensibility. The bad criticism, on the other hand, is that which
is nothing but an expression of emotion. And emotional people!such as
stockbrokers, politicians, men of science!and a few people who pride
themselves on being unemotional!detest or applaud great writers such as
Spinoza or Stendhal because of their "frigidity."
The writer of the present essay once committed himself to the statement that
"The poetic critic is criticizing poetry in order to create poetry."
He is now inclined to believe that the "historical" and the
"philosophical" critics had better be called historians and
philosophers quite simply. As for the rest, there are merely various degrees of
intelligence. It is fatuous to say that criticism is for the sake of
"creation" or creation for the sake of criticism. It is also fatuous
to assume that there are ages of criticism and ages of creativeness, as if by
plunging ourselves into intellectual darkness we were in better hopes of finding
spiritual light. The two directions of sensibility are complementary; and as
sensibility is rare, unpopular, and desirable, it is to be expected that the
critic and the creative artist should frequently be the same person.